In
mathematics
Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
, the epsilon numbers are a collection of
transfinite number
In mathematics, transfinite numbers or infinite numbers are numbers that are " infinite" in the sense that they are larger than all finite numbers. These include the transfinite cardinals, which are cardinal numbers used to quantify the size of i ...
s whose defining property is that they are
fixed points of an exponential map. Consequently, they are not reachable from 0 via a finite series of applications of the chosen exponential map and of "weaker" operations like addition and multiplication. The original epsilon numbers were introduced by
Georg Cantor
Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor ( ; ; – 6 January 1918) was a mathematician who played a pivotal role in the creation of set theory, which has become a foundations of mathematics, fundamental theory in mathematics. Cantor establi ...
in the context of
ordinal arithmetic; they are the
ordinal number
In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets.
A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
s ''ε'' that satisfy the
equation
In mathematics, an equation is a mathematical formula that expresses the equality of two expressions, by connecting them with the equals sign . The word ''equation'' and its cognates in other languages may have subtly different meanings; for ...
:
in which ω is the smallest infinite ordinal.
The least such ordinal is ''ε''
0 (pronounced epsilon nought (chiefly British), epsilon naught (chiefly American), or epsilon zero), which can be viewed as the "limit" obtained by
transfinite recursion
Transfinite induction is an extension of mathematical induction to well-ordered sets, for example to sets of ordinal numbers or cardinal numbers. Its correctness is a theorem of ZFC.
Induction by cases
Let P(\alpha) be a property defined for a ...
from a sequence of smaller limit ordinals:
:
where is the
supremum
In mathematics, the infimum (abbreviated inf; : infima) of a subset S of a partially ordered set P is the greatest element in P that is less than or equal to each element of S, if such an element exists. If the infimum of S exists, it is unique, ...
, which is equivalent to
set union
In set theory, the union (denoted by ∪) of a collection of sets is the set of all elements in the collection. It is one of the fundamental operations through which sets can be combined and related to each other.
A refers to a union of ze ...
in the case of the von Neumann representation of ordinals.
Larger ordinal fixed points of the exponential map are indexed by ordinal subscripts, resulting in
.
[Stephen G. Simpson, ''Subsystems of Second-order Arithmetic'' (2009, p.387)] The ordinal is still
countable
In mathematics, a Set (mathematics), set is countable if either it is finite set, finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function fro ...
, as is any epsilon number whose index is countable.
Uncountable
In mathematics, an uncountable set, informally, is an infinite set that contains too many elements to be countable. The uncountability of a set is closely related to its cardinal number: a set is uncountable if its cardinal number is larger tha ...
ordinals also exist, along with uncountable epsilon numbers whose index is an uncountable ordinal.
The smallest epsilon number appears in many
induction proofs, because for many purposes
transfinite induction is only required up to (as in
Gentzen's consistency proof and the proof of
Goodstein's theorem). Its use by
Gentzen to prove the consistency of
Peano arithmetic, along with
Gödel's second incompleteness theorem, show that Peano arithmetic cannot prove the
well-foundedness of this ordering (it is in fact the least ordinal with this property, and as such, in
proof-theoretic ordinal analysis, is used as a measure of the strength of the theory of Peano arithmetic).
Many larger epsilon numbers can be defined using the
Veblen function.
A more general class of epsilon numbers has been identified by
John Horton Conway and
Donald Knuth
Donald Ervin Knuth ( ; born January 10, 1938) is an American computer scientist and mathematician. He is a professor emeritus at Stanford University. He is the 1974 recipient of the ACM Turing Award, informally considered the Nobel Prize of comp ...
in the
surreal number
In mathematics, the surreal number system is a total order, totally ordered proper class containing not only the real numbers but also Infinity, infinite and infinitesimal, infinitesimal numbers, respectively larger or smaller in absolute value th ...
system, consisting of all surreals that are fixed points of the base ω exponential map .
defined gamma numbers (see
additively indecomposable ordinal
In set theory, a branch of mathematics, an additively indecomposable ordinal ''α'' is any ordinal number that is not 0 such that for any \beta,\gamma<\alpha, we have Additively indecomposable ordina ...
) to be numbers such that whenever , and delta numbers (see
multiplicatively indecomposable ordinal) to be numbers such that whenever , and epsilon numbers to be numbers such that whenever . His gamma numbers are those of the form , and his delta numbers are those of the form .
Ordinal ε numbers
The standard definition of
ordinal exponentiation with base α is:
*
*
when
has an immediate predecessor
.
*
, whenever
is a
limit ordinal
In set theory, a limit ordinal is an ordinal number that is neither zero nor a successor ordinal. Alternatively, an ordinal λ is a limit ordinal if there is an ordinal less than λ, and whenever β is an ordinal less than λ, then there exists a ...
.
From this definition, it follows that for any fixed ordinal , the
mapping is a
normal function, so it has arbitrarily large
fixed points by the
fixed-point lemma for normal functions. When
, these fixed points are precisely the ordinal epsilon numbers.
*
*
when
has an immediate predecessor
.
*
, whenever
is a limit ordinal.
Because
:
:
:
a different sequence with the same supremum,
, is obtained by starting from 0 and exponentiating with base instead:
:
Generally, the epsilon number
indexed by any ordinal that has an immediate predecessor
can be constructed similarly.
:
In particular, whether or not the index β is a limit ordinal,
is a fixed point not only of base ω exponentiation but also of base δ exponentiation for all ordinals
.
Since the epsilon numbers are an unbounded subclass of the ordinal numbers, they are enumerated using the ordinal numbers themselves. For any ordinal number
,
is the least epsilon number (fixed point of the exponential map) not already in the set
. It might appear that this is the non-constructive equivalent of the constructive definition using iterated exponentiation; but the two definitions are equally non-constructive at steps indexed by limit ordinals, which represent transfinite recursion of a higher order than taking the supremum of an exponential series.
The following facts about epsilon numbers are straightforward to prove:
* Although it is quite a large number,
is still
countable
In mathematics, a Set (mathematics), set is countable if either it is finite set, finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function fro ...
, being a countable union of countable ordinals; in fact,
is countable if and only if
is countable.
* The union (or supremum) of any
non-empty set of epsilon numbers is an epsilon number; so for instance
is an epsilon number. Thus, the mapping
is a normal function.
* The
initial ordinal of any
uncountable
In mathematics, an uncountable set, informally, is an infinite set that contains too many elements to be countable. The uncountability of a set is closely related to its cardinal number: a set is uncountable if its cardinal number is larger tha ...
cardinal
Cardinal or The Cardinal most commonly refers to
* Cardinalidae, a family of North and South American birds
**''Cardinalis'', genus of three species in the family Cardinalidae
***Northern cardinal, ''Cardinalis cardinalis'', the common cardinal of ...
is an epsilon number.
Representation of ε0 by rooted trees
Any epsilon number ε has
Cantor normal form , which means that the Cantor normal form is not very useful for epsilon numbers. The ordinals less than , however, can be usefully described by their Cantor normal forms, which leads to a representation of as the ordered set of all
finite rooted trees, as follows. Any ordinal
has Cantor normal form
where ''k'' is a
natural number
In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positive in ...
and
are ordinals with
, uniquely determined by
. Each of the ordinals
in turn has a similar Cantor normal form. We obtain the finite rooted tree representing α by joining the roots of the trees representing
to a new root. (This has the consequence that the number 0 is represented by a single root while the number
is represented by a tree containing a root and a single leaf.) An order on the set of finite rooted trees is defined recursively: we first order the subtrees joined to the root in decreasing order, and then use
lexicographic order
In mathematics, the lexicographic or lexicographical order (also known as lexical order, or dictionary order) is a generalization of the alphabetical order of the dictionaries to sequences of ordered symbols or, more generally, of elements of a ...
on these ordered sequences of subtrees. In this way the set of all finite rooted trees becomes a
well-ordered set which is
order isomorphic to .
This representation is related to the proof of the
hydra theorem, which represents decreasing sequences of ordinals as a
graph-theoretic game.
Veblen hierarchy
The fixed points of the "epsilon mapping"
form a normal function, whose fixed points form a normal function; this is known as the
Veblen hierarchy (the Veblen functions with base ). In the notation of the Veblen hierarchy, the epsilon mapping is , and its fixed points are enumerated by (see
ordinal collapsing function.)
Continuing in this vein, one can define maps for progressively larger ordinals α (including, by this rarefied form of transfinite recursion, limit ordinals), with progressively larger least fixed points . The least ordinal not reachable from 0 by this procedure—i. e., the least ordinal α for which , or equivalently the first fixed point of the map
—is the
Feferman–Schütte ordinal . In a set theory where such an ordinal can be proved to exist, one has a map that enumerates the fixed points , , , ... of
; these are all still epsilon numbers, as they lie in the image of for every , including of the map that enumerates epsilon numbers.
Surreal ε numbers
In ''
On Numbers and Games
''On Numbers and Games'' is a mathematics book by John Horton Conway first published in 1976. The book is written by a pre-eminent mathematician, and is directed at other mathematicians. The material is, however, developed in a playful and unpr ...
'', the classic exposition on
surreal number
In mathematics, the surreal number system is a total order, totally ordered proper class containing not only the real numbers but also Infinity, infinite and infinitesimal, infinitesimal numbers, respectively larger or smaller in absolute value th ...
s,
John Horton Conway provided a number of examples of concepts that had natural extensions from the ordinals to the surreals. One such function is the
-map ; this mapping generalises naturally to include all surreal numbers in its
domain, which in turn provides a natural generalisation of the
Cantor normal form for surreal numbers.
It is natural to consider any fixed point of this expanded map to be an epsilon number, whether or not it happens to be strictly an ordinal number. Some examples of non-ordinal epsilon numbers are
:
and
:
There is a natural way to define
for every surreal number ''n'', and the map remains
order-preserving
In mathematics, a monotonic function (or monotone function) is a function between ordered sets that preserves or reverses the given order. This concept first arose in calculus, and was later generalized to the more abstract setting of ord ...
. Conway goes on to define a broader class of "irreducible" surreal numbers that includes the epsilon numbers as a particularly interesting subclass.
See also
*
Ordinal arithmetic
*
Large countable ordinal
References
* J.H. Conway, ''On Numbers and Games'' (1976) Academic Press
* Section XIV.20 of
*
{{countable ordinals
Ordinal numbers